Back to H.F. Philosophy contents
INDICTMENTS OF CAPITALIST IMPERIALISM?
Henry Flynt
A. What needs indictment?
It is now a truism that there is a global economic
dichotomy between metropolis and hinterland, First World and Third World,[1] Northern
hemisphere and Southern hemisphere.
There is a large indignant literature which depicts this dichotomy, and
attempts to analyze it. In addition,
this dichotomy gave rise to a number of the large political ventures of the
twentieth century. The Soviet Union
always sought to carry on a war against Western or capitalist imperialism. Lenin said that the revolution came first to
backward Russia because it was “imperialism’s weakest link”—placing the
question of imperialism at the center of the Soviet Union’s existence. China, Cuba, Vietnam became towering symbols
of anti-imperialist partisanship. Peron
was associated with a mobilization of a Third-World country, Argentina, on a
path which his supporters saw as an alternative to Leftism. So-called bourgeois nationalist opposition
to imperialism was pursued by Krishna Menon and Sukarno, for example. The Vatican, which of course has a vast
constituency in Latin America, held its own conference on development planning
in the Sixties.[2] In the late Sixties, the economist Raul
Prebisch stepped forward as a spokesman for the Third World in the “responsible
institutions.” These examples do not
amount to a complete survey. They are
meant to remind the initiated reader how large and diverse a complete survey
would be.
Lately in the United States we have a youth radicalism,
the radicalism of rash intuitive men, which makes purity of indignation the
main consideration in its view of global wealth and poverty. To rip the System must be deliciously
transgressive and cathartic—but the rash intuitive man is left unaware of the
intellectual difficulties and political variations on the indignant side of the
fence.
The most obvious shortcoming of the rash intuitive men is
that they say nothing serious and responsible about what “we” should do
next. Are the intuitive men suggesting
that the differences between a Gandhi and a Mao are a mere subtlety that does
not matter? Are they suggesting that
you can tell by intuitive methods whether foreign investment is inherently
evil, and if we grant that it is, what is wrong with it?
Those who are intoxicated with the transgressiveness and
righteousness of denunciation have overlooked the requirements for a meaningful
and cogent politics or economic path.
The era of the revolutionary solutions is over—only time will tell
whether for the long term or the short term.
The era of the deeply considered revolutionaries such as Lenin, or even
Castro, is over; their ventures have ended in cataclysmic humiliation. Mao, Krishna Menon, Sukarno are not
especially heroes today. What is more,
Eastern Europe welcomed the epoch-making privatization managed by Harvard
economist Jeffrey Sachs. The realities
today do not leave anybody in an economic decision-making position anywhere in
the world the luxury to fly off the handle with indignation.
Academic economics glories in the private-enterprise
principles which presumably have produced the global dichotomy—such as
comparative advantage and free movement of capital. Michael Hudson emphasized that a century ago, there were
conservative arguments against colonialism, and in favor of trade barriers—but
this lesson has hardly been a beacon in our time. One who wants to oppose the global disparity by deeds—whether
Lenin or Prebisch—may well prepare those deeds with a theory of why global
private enterprise has an outcome which is “unjust.” Since academic economics does not permit the conclusion that
“free enterprise” exploits—regarding it as no better than a claim that the
earth is flat—one who wants to substantiate “unjust relations” has to go off
the reservation theoretically. The
appeal was usually made to Marx’s economics, although perhaps not always.
Thus, there is an entire intellectual tradition of
theories of European imperialism. There
is a helpful book in this regard, Alan Hodgart, The Economics of European Imperialism (1977). Hodgart notes every passage in Capital and Theories of Surplus Value which pertains to “international or
colonial economics.” He then reviews a
roster of theorists which I would expand slightly: Hobson, Hilferding, Kautsky, Lenin, Luxemburg, Bukharin, Baran
and Sweezy, Prebisch, Jalée, Emmanuel, Bettelheim. Many of these figures resemble each other, and differ from any
academic economist, in that their explicit goal is indictment of transactions
between the advanced and underveloped countries which have been legal: such as private foreign investment and the
international exchange of raw materials for manufactured goods. In other words, these authors explicitly
aspire to theorize a war, a war which has the arcane artificiality of
finance. To coin a phrase, they are militant theorists.[3] Their results may be judged by whether they
are intellectually convincing, and in that regard our theorists disagreed bitterly,
casting aspersions not only on each other’s logic, but on each other’s
loyalties. Their results may also be
judged by how they want to strategize the war.
Here again, our theorists expressed intense hatreds for each other. (Lenin on Kautsky should be enough to make
the point.)
This essay is entirely concerned with analyses of
capitalist imperialism in this heterodox tradition, the tradition of militant
theory. It must be said, again, that
the deeply considered, hard-fought revolutions of the twentieth century have
lately ended in cataclysmic humiliation.
Some insurgencies, such as that in Argentina, became tragic before they
could win anything. The cause of
privatization and free markets has won massive allegiance around the
world. Revolution is not the order of
the day. My concern is with the
prospects of the theoretical appraisals of imperialism.[4]
Somebody who wants to settle the matter by sheer purity
of indignation needs to be presented with the following questions.
—Was Peron a good guy or a bad
guy?
—Should the poor countries
solve their poverty problem by securing greater profits for their capitalists?
—Should the poor countries
build heavy industries of their own, no matter the hardship? (Mao, Krishna Menon)
—Should the rich nations steer
more investment to the poor nations?
—Canada’s economy is largely
foreign-owned, mostly by the U.S. Is
Canada cruelly oppressed by the U.S.?
—Was Western Europe a victim
of U.S. imperialism up to the day that the U.S. became a net debtor nation—and
was the U.S. a victim nation thereafter?
—Are the reforms which made
First-World capitalism less draconian to be admired—or despised as bribes
forestalling the revolution?
—Given that the rich countries
are rich, does that mean that their inhabitants effectively comprise a single
rich class? (No class divisions in
Europe, Canada?)
—Does (or did) Communist China
enjoy the good life because it is, in fact, Third-World and Communist?
—Is China oppressing Tibet,
economically or otherwise?
—Was the Soviet Union
responsible for relationships that could be called imperialist, in East Europe
or in East Africa?
•
B. Aims of militant
economics
Let me propose a broad characterization of the aims of
economic theory, and of the empirical observations which motivate theory and to
which theory has to respond.
The well-being of populations is dependent on work and
technology. Production is stratified by
ownership and subordination. All this
is implemented in human transactions which are minutely quantified and proceed
in intricate circuits. The
transformation of human provisioning and human gratification into trading and
prices mediates the material processes—and in the longer run transforms their
character. High-level abstractions such
as the creation of money by central banking and the derivatives markets exert
immense power over people’s well-being.
We may, then, demand an explanation of this artificial and quantified
reality which governs the population’s well-being.
The student of so-called international economics has to
address the following observations.
—After the decolonization of
1960, the evident polarization of independent nations into rich and poor
nations (on the basis of GNP per capita, if you will).
—The claim, whether true or
not, that as far as trade between nations is concerned, poor nations were
surrendering ever-increasing quantities of their raw materials in return for
manufactured goods. (The terms-of-trade
accusation.)
—The gap in wage rates between
nations.
—The preference on the part of
rich nations for investing in other rich nations.
—While there may be a case for
premium profits in the least developed countries, it is not an open-and-shut
case.
—Canada as the nation with the
most foreign ownership of its economy, and the nation receiving the most U.S.
investment.
—Capital flight from poor
nations to rich nations.
—The change in the status of
the U.S. from net capital exporter to net capital importer.
—Private foreign investment is
only a small fraction in dollars of total U.S. economic activity.
—Profits from investments in
underdeveloped countries are only a small fraction in dollars of total U.S.
income.
—The intergovernmental
financial arrangements, from Bretton Woods in 1944 to their unilateral
abrogation by the United States in 1971—and up until today.
—A country can get a trade
advantage over other countries by weakening its currency.
—The beneficial effect of
massive foreign ownership in Canada; but not in Guatemala, for example.
—Successful development—escape
from underdevelopment—by nations of the Pacific rim.
—The absence of large
financial panics and world depression after World War II.
—Growing transfer of
manufactures to the Third World, the former raw materials producers. The new importance, as low-wage labor, of
populations which “underclass” theories conceived as expendable.
—Third-World debt,
catastrophic currency devaluations, bail-outs of national economies by the
I.M.F.
We ask whether
these phenomena, which are all collective human creations, have explanations in
terms of processes considered elementary, or material. (In other words, nonpecuniary.) How do financial magnitudes encode
“physical” and “psychological” realities when an entire system of transactions
or circuits is taken into view?
Indeed that is
where fundamental theory would have to start—and the question has answers on
different levels.
• How the U.S.S.R. transformed life in the Asian republics.
• How naked coercion assembled a global hinterland in the first
place.
• How some basic ensemble of pecuniary circuits steers nonpecuniary
realities of work, consumption, acquisition.
• Turning it around, how pecuniary processes are shifted by material
changes (one imagines as an example the depletion of a country’s oil
reserves).
I have extensive writings
which are meant to be suggestive in these areas. I don’t claim to have gotten to the bottom of it. In any case, it is the only way I can
propose out of the Marxist blind alley.
The task which militant theory sets itself is to explain the manifest degradation of
populations: in terms of transactions
mechanisms translatable into material processes. To prove that the observed polarization of nations into rich and
poor is the result of a legal transactions mechanism which exploits. (Which is an
unequal exchange—which appropriates without equivalent.) The aim was to find a conceptual scheme, a
transactions mechanism, buttressed by data, which incriminates international
transactions which are fully legal.[5]
•
While the emphasis here is explicitly on indictment, it
is well to note certain objective conditions which placed the regions which
first were colonies, then poor nations, at a disadvantage in a capitalist
world.
—Some regions started behind
the goal posts in that they had not reached the feudal level of social
development when modern colonialism began.
—Some nations, as collectives,
want what hinders capitalist transformation.
Cultural choices which are unsuited to total commercialization.
—Some national governments are
said to have strategized badly, to have taken the wrong turn when they didn’t
have to. Argentina.
These considerations become
most prominent when backwardness is equated
with safeguarding the nation from
imperialism. If underdeveloped
nations cling to antique religious positions such as Islamic fundamentalism, or
the “Church of the poor” (as the Latin American Church is called), they have no
warrant for measuring fairness by rapidity of modernization. If instantaneous lateral
communication—satellite, fax, Internet—was not encouraged in Eighties Iran,
that was because of a local cultural condition.[6]
Some of the poor countries are dictatorships, such that
all increases in payments to the country would be appropriated by the dictator
and banked outside his country. To
indulge such a state of affairs does not better the condition of the poor. On the other hand: to act from without to end the dictatorship would be interference
in the nation’s internal affairs.[7]
•
In this essay, I do not at all propose to review the
sequence of theories since Capital. Let me only say that the project of militant
theory has never been carried out to the satisfaction of any public other than
a sectarian one. The concern of this
essay is to work through a recent proposal for a diachronic indictment of capitalist imperialism. I end with some of my recent thoughts about
militant theory.
•
C. The ground-plan
Marx thought that he had identified the elemental
capitalist act which “steals,” which appropriates without equivalent. It was presented in Capital as the c-v-s analysis, which subsequently encounters the
transformation of values into prices, and the falling rate of profit, as
hurdles. Chapter II of my Ph.D.
dissertation, The Theory of Socialist
Economic Administration (1978), was devoted to the algebraic gist of the
argument of Capital; I shall take it
as my reference when a non-judgmental paraphrase is wanted.[8] What has to be said is that the c-v-s
analysis and the cogency of the transformation of values into prices have not
been vindicated for any public other than a sectarian one. It seems fair to say that most academic
economists who declare themselves sympathetic to Marx believe that the core of
his theory was a failure.[9]
But for the sake of argument, let us proceed as if Marx’s
core notions could be salvaged. Then we
need to ask, what is the elemental imperialist
act in the capitalist era? The question
posed by imperialism is an obscure one.
Lenin found the elemental imperialist act in foreign investment to reap
premium profits; others find it in the trade of raw materials for manufactured
goods. But just this question of the
elemental imperialist act has not been settled.
All the same, Marx and Lenin supplied us with a clue
which must be the cornerstone of the analysis.
Imperialism is not alien to capitalism; imperialism is a relation
between regions of the earth already operative during the mercantilistic era—antedating the multilateral sovereignty which is
the premise of international economic exchanges today.
National
economic activity is already parcelled out among different firms: which battle with each other on many levels
even while their simultaneous law-abiding aggrandizement[10]
establishes the uniformities which make the aggrandizement possible.
The world economy is segmented by national
boundaries. At any given moment,
nations are at markedly different stages in the modernization process. (Nations may even renounce modernity as a
goal.) In the past, some nations
nakedly oppressed others, pushing the latter behind the goal posts. Now we are in the midst of transactions
between nations under capitalist rules.
What is more, there is a discernable capitalist imperative: commodification steadily penetrates
societies everywhere and seizes control of them.
•
D. Background sketches, Marx
and Lenin
The indictments of capitalism and imperialism by Marx and
Lenin were carefully crafted analyses, with definite and narrow political
consequences. Marx’s indictment of
capitalism, or wage labor, was rigorously synchronic
and self-contained. Although Marx believed himself an expert on
economic history, and wrote with great indignation about the history of
capitalism, his central contribution concerned a highly simplified uniform
capitalism. Marx wanted to address the
pure principle of capitalism. He wanted
to show that capitalism steals from the worker in principle; that elimination
of the imperfections of competition, increases in wages, etc. cannot make this
theft less real, even if temporary improvements in conditions gain the
acquiescence of workers to their servitude.
Marx argued that exactly what is legal under bourgeois
justice, exactly what is argued as a just bargain by such thinkers as Adam
Smith, is the very essence of thievery and exploitation.
Indeed, Marx sought to make an even stronger case which
denied that reform could ever make capitalism harmonious. Rising wages would always be a threat to
employers, and they would always find a way to beat back wages or escape from
high wages. Capitalist competition
would always be reckless, and would never stop jarring and dislocating
society. The reduction of all goals to
money would never stop wounding the individual psyche.
In Marx’s pure capitalist model, the economy inside a
single nation was treated as absolutely self-contained. If there were transactions with the outside
at all, they were purchases or sales of goods from other sovereign
nations. Thus, Marx’s core analysis of
capitalism had no colonialism and did not see colonialism as intrinsic to
capitalism.
According to Rosa Luxemburg,[11] the
model of expanded reproduction of Volume 2 of Capital was invalid for this reason. According to her, the colonial outlet was indispensable to
capitalism. Capitalism had to go outside
the nation because it could not survive unless it could constantly enlarge the
market. There never had been, and never
would be, a viable capitalism confined within national boundaries, conducting a
purely intranational exploitation; such that nations related to one another
solely as sovereign equals.
But again, there was a reason for Marx’s intranational
model. Marx wanted to prove that the
transactions involved in the system of wage labor cheated the worker
intrinsically. Capitalism could not, by
bringing itself nearer the ideal of perfect competition, or political equality
and autonomy of the actors, transform itself into a beneficent
institution. If Marx could not have
confined the model to the capitalists and workers of one nation—if he had had
to take an intercontinental model as the minimum unit, granting that capitalist
transformation had not occurred in the colony—he would not have been able to
carry out his quantification of exactly what the capitalists stole from the
workers.
Luxemburg’s critics saw all too well that her correction
of Marx in fact scuttled the Marxist project, because it left the theory
without any quantified proof of unequal exchange, relying on a purely
impressionistic perception of injustice.
Luxemburg’s correction was understandably ignored by the Marxist
faithful. Indeed, when events compelled
them to try to make a Marxist appraisal of colonialism, they did so by simply
applying Marx’s encapsulated model to the case in which the capitalists are in
one nation and the workers are in another.
The encapsulated model was made to cover Luxemburg’s case by stretching
its mechanism over the extraterritoriality whose disregard invalidated the
model in the first place. It is a
commonplace in science, to stretch the model which is invalid because of the cases it excludes to explain the
cases it excludes.
Another point to remember in applying Marx to colonialism
is that Marx did not consider natural resources to have any value. Only when natural resources were worked did
that confer value on them. There was no
theft involved in depletion as such.
There was no such thing as ecology.
•
When Lenin decided to write about imperialism, there
already was a literature on imperialism by J.A. Hobson, Rudolf Hilferding, Karl
Kautsky (in Die Neue Zeit)—a
literature which struggled to appraise the significance of the international
oligopolies called “trusts” in the era in which Asia and Africa had just been
divided among the nations of Europe.
Lenin chose to carry forward the precedent of Marx. He did not base his argument on the
enslavement and plunder of the colonial era.
In fact, he went to the opposite extreme. Like Marx, he focused on a pure and uniform network of economic
transactions, namely direct foreign investment (perhaps with foreign loans).
Lenin denounced foreign investment as imperialism at a
time when other social critics believed that imperialism could only consist in
the annexation of territory: in the
occupation of one country by the army of another, and the instillation of a
“consular” regime in the former country by the latter (e.g. the British Viceroy
in India). The leader of the Second
International, Kautsky, said that only annexation of territory was imperialism. Lenin found the essence of imperialism in
economic transactions which were legal and which other thinkers considered
indispensable to modern economy (and so not imperialist at all).
This juncture invites bitter controversy, and we should
not pass over it casually. The word
‘imperialism’ is a pejorative generic.
It means that the organized inhabitants of one territory overrun those
of another, and appropriate wealth from them coercively. (Even if it has the legal veil of tax
collection, etc.) Archaeologists
introduce the word ‘imperialism’ in connection with ancient Egyptian
civilization. The question, then, is
how far we can go in redefining the word when we suspect that we are seeing a
new mechanism of economic domination.
An inhabitant of the Soviet bloc could have said that the relation of
the Soviet Union to Poland or Czechoslovakia or Hungary was imperialist. If he had, he would have been shot.
Lenin knew about the piratical epoch of European
colonialism, about the days of the slave trade and the East India Company and
all the rest of it. He denounced the
League of Nations as a thieves’ kitchen; and the U.S.S.R. planned out a global
strategy of Asian anti-colonialism. But
that is not what Lenin chose to write about in his classic tract. His title suggested that capitalism came
last to imperialism, not first to it.
He treated an antiseptic and legal branch of international commerce,
namely direct foreign investment (and perhaps also foreign loans or borrowing). As with Marx and capitalism, Lenin wanted to
prove that this practice was intrinsically exploitive. Presumably it was so for a highly abstract
reason, that the investor nation extracted surplus value, in the Marxist sense,
from the labor force of the nation hosting the investment. A transfer of surplus value from one nation
to another. Certainly there would be a
marked wage difference between the two regions. The falling rate of profit may have come into it. The decline in profit had not gone as far in
the underdeveloped countries as in the metropolitan countries. That allowed foreign investors to reap
premium profits.
So Lenin saw the relevant imperialism as new, not
old. Its core was defined not by
European transactions with other continents, but by transformation of capital
structure in the metropolis. Imperialism
was a late phase of capitalism (late to Lenin, not to us) in which banks gained
hegemony in the economies of the metropolitan countries. The financial activity of these banks beyond
the frontiers of the host nation was the key to imperialist theft—not the
acquisition of territories to be governed by “consuls” from the
metropolis. The Rockefeller banks in
Latin America: that was imperialism. By emphasizing international financial
transactions over the annexation and direct governance of other countries,
Lenin actually made himself more relevant to the decades which followed his
death—the decades of decolonization and the burgeoning of purely monetary
“exploitation” of the Third World.
•
Next we have to turn back to Marx. After political thought was sensitized to
the importance of colonialism, students wanted to elaborate a theory from clues
found in the Master’s works. I have
already recounted that Luxemburg proposed to undercut Marx’s core analysis on the very issue of imperialism;
but students chose to look past her objection back to the Master. Marx’s work was raked over minutely, and a
sentence here and a sentence there were pulled out and stretched to become
entire theories.
The key passage, perhaps, is page 238 of Volume 3 of Capital (New York, International
Publishers, 1967). On this page two
accusations are hurled against the developed countries. According to one, the rate of profit falls
in the developed country (because production becomes more and more
capital-intensive). Thus the developed
country pours capital into the undeveloped country to gain a higher rate of
profit there.
In the second indictment, it is the developed country
which is found nefariously to have the higher rate of profit, because the shift
to capital-intensive production lowers the wage bill associated with given
manufactures. Since the market price is
globally parametric, the advanced country which sells at this price enjoys a
temporary manufacturer’s surplus; thus it gains a surplus profit when it exchanges its products with those of the
undeveloped country.
The accusations find the developed country’s gain to stem
from both its profit premium and the victimized country’s profit premium. To propose that both contingencies are in
force at once is not brilliant, because all value theory requires an
equilibrium resulting from capital rushing to the most profitable
opportunity. (I don’t remember any
provision for capital to rush in opposite directions at the same time.) Marx’s ruminations, in what after all were
unpublished notes, fail to comprise a cogent theory. What is so disappointing for one who wants a Communist world is
that militant theory has decided that we must make a meal of these spoiled
scraps or else starve. We are even
supposed to forget the challenge on colonialism that Capital incurred from Luxemburg.
•
E. The diachronic indictment
— capitalism
A different avenue of righteous denunciation of Western
imperialism may be proposed—the diachronic indictment. Imperialist injustice is proved from a
specific course of history which began five hundred years ago, no earlier and
no later.[12]
The diachronic indictment finds injustice to be a prima
facie issue. Relations between the West
and the Third World were unjust because they involved conquest or
coercion. They were unjust because they found one party to be rich and the
other to be poor at the completion of the transaction. If the West can wield any sort of power over
the Third World, and is better off than the latter, then the former oppresses the latter. To
possess an advantage is inherently evil.
A drawback of this approach is so obvious that we cannot
postpone mentioning it. It is merely
humanitarian, face-value, undialectical.
It makes no attempt to understand what drives manifest change in the
institutions, the mechanisms.[13] It takes its stand on visible
relationships. It is not cognizant that
social development proceeds in reversals of face-value conditions.
And beyond that, the diachronic indictment imagines that
it makes sense to render moral judgments on strategic
advantages. To be consistent
relative to its five-hundred year perspective, the diachronic indictment would
have to judge the Scientific Revolution to have been evil. Marxism, at least, had already settled accounts
with reactionary utopianism. But we
find that reactionary utopianism is always with us.
Notwithstanding any objections, I wish to pursue the
diachronic indictment to see if we learn anything from it.
By implication, a diachronic indictment of capitalism can
be made. In the beginning, capitalism
had no child labor laws, no compulsory education, no minimum wage. What is more important is that there is
nothing in the principle of capitalism which requires these constraints, these
parameters, these floors and ceilings.
On the contrary, rigorous laissez-faire doctrine finds all political
constraints to be interferences and aberrations.
In the mid-nineteenth century, the worker went into the
factory at age six, and did not leave it until he or she was ready to die. Workers purchased their provisions at the
company store, in fact or in effect.
Wages did not rise above the level of corporeal survival—and in fact,
the worker was routinely abused so that he or she died early. Female employees were sexually at the mercy
of employers. One can argue, then, that
the result of this capitalism, which was the most pure capitalism, was
indistinguishable from slavery.
A new mechanism replicated slavery’s capture of the
laborer. The diachronic indictment observes:
At the end of the fiscal year, the outcomes of slavery and of early
capitalism, as far as the laborer is concerned, are more or less the same. Different transactions mechanisms have
secured more or less the same results. Again,
this draconian capitalism is the most authentic capitalism, capitalism
unencumbered with politically imposed constraints on markets. Somehow, this point has not been given
sufficient attention. Laissez-faire
doctrine says that the form of the employment bargain guarantees that it is
just. “A day’s work for a day’s
pay.” But the employment bargain
imposes the same existence on the workers that slavery does.
Free-market ideology finds only one way in which
capitalism can be unfair. A monopoly
vendor or purchaser can reap a windfall profit because his customers or
suppliers are his captives, they have nowhere else to go. (Laissez-faire ideology argues that
protectionism was wrong, we may remember.
It is wrong for weak countries to bar entry to the goods and capital
from strong countries.)
After the twentieth century begins, there are reforms
concerning child labor, compulsory education, factory safety, a minimum
wage. These reforms are not driven by
the capitalist principle itself. They
come from humanitarian activists, or for that matter, from labor
radicalism. They are interferences with
the market.
Nevertheless, as a result of these reforms, the
capitalist result begins to diverge markedly from slavery. Children have a childhood in which they are
inculcated with competences rather than producing. They spend ten years on the educational assembly line before
moving to the production line. Consumer
choices matter (and matter greatly).
Workers acquire assets and have some personal goals. For the capitalist, these reforms are both
an opportunity and a challenge. The
worker becomes far more promising as a consumer, as a market for the
capitalist’s wares. At the same time,
rising real wages spur the capitalist to battle back in the only ways
available, introduction of labor-saving technology, and transfer of
manufactures to low-wage environments.
Humanitarian restrictions on cutthroat capitalism, then,
prove to be the catalyst for capitalism’s development to a higher stage.
All of this takes place before the most celebrated reform
of capitalism, the New Deal and the mixed economy. Now, for example, labor unions achieve statutory recognition and
exemption from prosecution for monopolizing the labor supply.
So something happens which Marx’s synchronic analysis
does not really capture—even though Marx was keenly cognizant of post-feudal
and colonial history, primitive accumulation and all the rest of it.
The rules of the capitalist game do not produce a unique
sociological outcome. They are
compatible with several sociologically distinct outcomes. This proves, first, that there is a historical cross-over point at which
the different forms of the transaction, as between capitalism and slavery,
secure more or less the same results as far as the laborer is concerned.
What is more, to the degree that capitalism later
differentiates itself from slavery, it is because restrictions on the free
market are forced on capitalism by clergymen and labor radicals; in other
words, the system is redeemed against its own will and principle.
On the other hand, as capitalism is reformed, there is a
prima facie, sociologically definable divergence of the worker’s life from the
slave's life. Indeed, the consumer
markets, and consumer durables markets, of late capitalism would be impossible
without increases in earnings and the expansion of the worker’s discretion.[14] There is also the element of the large
middle class which may, above all, characterize an “advanced democracy.” But the middle class means different things: the old middle class is the small business,
the family farm or the store; the new middle class is corporate management and
the professions, or the entire white-collar population.
Of course, while all this affluence is accumulating, the capitalist is moving the manufacturing operation farther and farther away from the metropolis, into regions where fair labor practices laws have not yet penetrated.
If the diachronic indictment is a good analysis, then it
disproves Marx, or at least would make him very uncomfortable. If you judge the justice of an economic
system by its result, and assume that the rationale of transactions is only a
costume, and does not constitute an agenda capable of molding the course of events, then perhaps capitalism becomes less
and less wicked as the early injustices are cleared away.
It is deeper than that.
We assume that slavery is evil prima facie; then capitalism is evil
because at its inception it has the import of slavery. The farther we get from slavery, the farther
we move into moral limbo. If capitalism
becomes unlike slavery, then we don’t know whether it is good or bad. Perhaps we could reach a point where the
wage bargain is completely fair.
Otherwise, the diachronic indictment could move with the
times. One can find plenty to decry in
today’s world, plenty of disparities in wealth and power. But you have to move the template. To call “slavery” what goes on inside the
regions of modernized capitalism is willfully oblivious—for the reasons already
spelled out.
We may imagine Marx saying, the world does not end with
capitalism, it begins with it.
Capitalism is a problem unto itself.
It does not matter what it resembles.
When capitalism becomes a distinct formation, at that moment, it is
perfectly “unfair.” What is more, the capitalist
form, the specific capitalist rationale, is quite capable of generating a
social order unique to it. It creates
previously unheard-of stresses and shocks such as financial panics, and
unemployment resulting from financial contraction. Further, it creates a climate in which selfish financial
virtuosity is humanity’s only goal.
Even with the growing comfort of the “labor aristocracy,” there is also
a growing artificiality or abstractness of life, since qualities no longer
matter, and human greatness is narrowed to the ingenuity of the stockbroker (a
combination of arithmetical adeptness and shrewd divination).[15] Even those performances which are not
defined by money, such as athletics or music, are now judged by the
multimillion dollar incomes of the most successful performers.
As we re-examine indictments of capitalism—that is, of
wage labor—we arrive at a new perception of radical politics. Capitalism has been found to be as bad as
slavery because it can yield the same result.
Or, Marx would say, the wage bargain, the transactions mechanism, is a
theft in any case. But then what do
radicals want? We may be surprised to
learn that they all have the same immediate demand: more jobs.
“To address the near-record levels
of unemployment, we call for a shorter workweek at no loss in pay to provide
jobs for all.”
Australasian Sparticist,
Spring 1997
“Decent jobs are clearly the answer to most of what ails us.”
John C. Cort, in The Catholic Worker, August-September 1997
After carefully proving that
capitalism is the same as slavery, or is theft in any case, they rush forward
demanding to be abused. The demand to
be abused is the immediate demand of radicalism.
Either they don’t understand what their own words mean,
or else capitalism is the only way in which they can imagine the production of
the social product will ever be effected.
Claims to the contrary are theatrics and bluster.
It is even more ridiculous than that. A Communist sect in Italy (the ICC)
carefully explains that the New Deal was a capitalist trick. It declares in its program that bourgeois
democracy is the same thing as fascism.
It then denounces the U.S. politician Gingrich for recently annulling
the provisions of the New Deal. “We
demand that you continue to trick us, you fascist!”
•
F. The diachronic indictment
of capitalist imperialism
The diachronic indictment comes into its own with respect
to colonialism and imperialism. Today,
no ideologue of justice wants to defend the era in which Europe enriched itself
by naked conquest and population transfers (settlement).[16] All of colonialism involved what would now
be called crimes; dispossession of aboriginal populations and the slave
economies were crimes against humanity.
The first proscription of the slave trade at the international
diplomatic level was announced by England in 1806. The first condemnation of annexation of nations at the
international diplomatic level was President Wilson’s Fourteen Principles of
1918.
But what of the “modern, democratic” era, in which
nations relate economically without annexation of territory? Let us look at the operation of U.S. firms
such as Standard Oil, United Fruit, ITT, the Rockefeller banks in Latin America
or the Middle East. Or, for that
matter, we could go back to the Monroe doctrine, in which the U.S. claimed
Latin America even though it did not annex it or formally undertake to govern
it.
What we see, relative to US. capitalism, is a historical
cross-over point at which the only difference between foreign investment and
literal, European-style colonialism is in the form of the transaction. Sociologically, we find an exercise of
hegemony of the U.S. over Latin America as blatant as the French exercise of hegemony
over Indochina, for example.
When the U.S. determines that its interests in another
country are threatened, it unilaterally invades; or it intervenes when it is
invited in by a friendly ruler to protect him from a domestic rebellion. Because the U.S. is more advanced, and
larger than any Latin country, it can wield monopoly power relative to
individual Latin countries, and bribe their governments. In addition, there is a long-standing claim
that there is an inherent disadvantage in being a raw materials supplier.[17]
•
The lesson is that there is no development in Marx’s model; Marx had no vision of what we now call
development. He said that capitalism
would get bigger in total, and more centralized;[18] but
at the same time that it would grind toward pauperization and catastrophe. Marx did not ascribe a long-term historic
mission to capitalism, a mission of ascending to ever greater wealth,
ever more advanced technology, ever changing industrial and occupational
structures, increasing comfort for mass populations.
From the case of various underdeveloped countries, we
learn that a nation can be drawn into the network of capitalist transactions
without experiencing spreading prosperity, expansion of real manufactured
wealth, marked technological transformation.
But for Marx, it was merely that one nation was farther along on the path than another. Different nations did not have capitalisms
which were complementary in essence. Marx had no opportunity to analyze the case
of nations which failed for decades to develop in the post-colonial era.
Marx had posited that capitalism went through a necessary
phase of assembly of a labor force via
expropriation. The capitalist had
to generate a class to which he did not belong: a propertyless population which would consent to poverty
wages. When wages are pushed up, the
capitalist has to shift to labor-saving technology to get more out of what the
wage pays for; but he also has to find cheaper workers. (A recession is the capitalist equivalent of
calling a strike on your own position.
It’s more important that wages are rolled back than that some businesses
will fail.)
What was not spelled out was a colonial equivalent to
this assembly of the labor force.[19] Marx did not say that international capitalism
must have different capitalisms which are essentially counterposed. For world capitalism to function, some
nations must wield power beyond the transaction in order to put other nations
at an economic disadvantage. This is
what accounts for the observed process:
in which the richest nations keep imposing new rules, keep shifting the
ground of the battle. It’s not a
generic transactions mechanism; it’s the counterposition of the capitalisms.
Then the proportion of transactions with underdeveloped countries
in the total economic activity of the developed country is not decisive. So:
when some nations put others at a commercial disadvantage, what effect
in particular do they seek? Cheap raw
materials; cheap labor; consumer markets:
in that order.
All the same, this is not a general theory of
international economic activity, because it leaves unexplained the greatest
volume of activity, which is between nations whose roles are parallel, not
diametrically opposed. But then
relations between companies are not primary in Marx’s analysis of capitalism,
for that matter.
•
The word ‘imperialism’ already carries the connotation of
oppression, as does the word ‘slavery’.
To indict imperialism means to
find that transactions between different territories consist in theft,
plunder. The question, then, is whether
commerce consists in theft, plunder.
We are not concerned here with the cultural dimensions of
imperialism. Whether cultural
imperialism is a generic offense such as imposing a foreign language or
religion on a population (Arabic and English, Islam and Christianity, in East
Africa). Or whether it is a specific
offense, the specific impositions of Europe’s civilization, the asceticism of
the Church, the spirituality of Leibniz and Kant, the aesthetics of Beethoven,
industrialization, scientific depersonalization, technification. Mercenary pragmatism.
As we see, the diachronic indictment does not pronounce
on whether there is a financial mechanism of interaction between rich nations
and poor nations which would be “unjust” between
any pair of nations.
The diachronic indictment invites certain groups of
questions.
1. When would economic interaction between nations be “just”? Is there a price for goods at which capitalist transactions become “just”? Does capitalism have to abolished before exchanges can be “just”? Do nations have to be abolished before economics can be “just”?
2. Are there imperialisms which are qualitatively more novel than, say, American banking in Latin America? What about the Soviet Union in East Europe?
Let me expand on (1) indirectly by considering how the
question of what should happen was answered by certain political
tendencies. When the Soviet Union still
possessed some credibility, it imposed a dogmatic perspective on international
commerce. Foreign ownership was
absolutely forbidden. A country which
went Communist was supposed to close its borders to capital. It was supposed to industrialize behind
politically simulated protectionism.
Righteous commercial relations were represented by trade between the
Soviet Union and the bloc nations, between the Soviet Union and Cuba. These were not claimed to be equal
exchanges. They incorporated
politically motivated subsidies. The
Soviet Union unilaterally dictated what the appropriate subsidies were. There was a trading bloc called CMEA (or
COMECON by Western propaganda).
Relations in this bloc were righteous international economics.
Let me expand on (2).
Was the role of Soviet Russia in the Soviet Union and CMEA
“imperialist”? In the decades in which
the Left defined itself by its support of the Soviet Union, it denied that this
new situation, found distressing by many including the Right, was an
imperialism. Subsequently the question
would be asked about China-Vietnam relations.
That is not all.
Some thinkers always accused the Soviet Union of practicing capitalism
via another mechanism, a mechanism in which the managerial class comprised the
“collective capitalist” and enjoyed political control of the means of
production (as opposed to individual ownership). This theory was widely ridiculed. Then Communism collapsed.
When privatization was announced, ownership of the factories immediately
devolved to the men who had been their managers under Communism. You can make of that what you will.
What of the episode in which Harvard economist Jeffrey
Sachs orchestrated the “restoration of capitalism in Communist Europe”? Transition from Communism to
capitalism. The world had never seen
anything like it. The nations in
question had solicited Sachs’ consultancy, of course.
By the Seventies, there were economists in U.S.
universities who had been radicalized by the Counter-Culture, having never
harkened to official Soviet doctrine.
These economists easily assumed that the metropolitan countries had
oppressed the colonial world by not investing enough in it; and that what the
radical Third World wanted today was a flood of investment from the First
World. To an initiate of the Old Left,
this sounds like victims demanding to be raped. But it was not only being heard from U.S. radical
economists. It was heard from Prebisch,
and later from African representatives.
°
As regards U.S. foreign investment, the diachronic
indictment finds a historical cross-over
point at which the only difference between foreign investment and literal
colonialism is in the form of the transaction.
But there is a key difference as between capitalism as
such, and imperialism, in this regard.
Capitalism at the cross-over was already pure or perfect. In order to remove the injustice, it had to
be reformed in a way which cut into market freedom. Foreign investment at the cross-over, however, was perhaps far
from perfect by laissez-faire doctrine.
The role of the Rockefellers in Latin America and the Middle East, for
example, obviously had illicit monopolistic and coercive aspects.
In any case, it is a devastating blow to free market and
free trade ideology to point out that international finance, without territorial
annexation, replicated the effect of literal colonialism. Even if the result could in part be blamed
on illicit distortions of competition.
And does anybody claim that monopoly and infringement of sovereignty by
force are not considerations today?
In the course of the second half of the twentieth
century, international economic relations underwent some sort of
face-lift. Raw-materials suppliers now
have cartels such as OPEC. Many
Third-World countries have manufacturing sectors. East Asia has escaped the underdevelopment trap. The U.S. itself is a net debtor nation.
Beyond OPEC, various proposals have been made to remedy
the supposed injustice. Talk of an
income tax on rich nations. Talk of
debt cancellation by Latin America.
Significantly, the latter never became a reality because the destruction
of the international financial structure would have hurt the poor countries
more than the rich ones. Factually,
underdeveloped countries clamor today for investment. Political tendencies which found the solution in nationalization
and exclusion of the foreign investor simply have no appeal today.
As for protectionism, it tends to be supported by labor
unions—and to be opposed by the far Left.
The U.S. cannot really be said to have foresworn military
intervention, because it continues to conduct proxy wars in other nations, with
or without legal cover. In the
tradition of the O.D. of the C.I.A.
As of 1997, Lenin’s absolute position that the investing
nation is the exploiter and the host nation is the victim does not enjoy
automatic credibility. An advanced
nation may be a net debtor nation; thus it would be a victim according to this
theory. Profits are high not only in
underdeveloped countries. Further,
underdeveloped countries desperately solicit foreign investment—none more so
than regimes which exist in spite of the United States, such as China and
Vietnam.
•
G. Reservations about the
diachronic indictment
How does the diachronic indictment of imperialism fare as
we examine the specific historical course toward century’s end? We still find vast disparities between
advanced and backward nations. The
exchange between the two develops the former but not the latter. On the other hand, some former Third-World
nations have developed and have become capitalist powers. (Mainly in East Asia. That leads to the surmise that East Asia
could not be kept subordinate because it was socially far enough along to develop.)
According to some denunciations of imperialism, it should not have been
possible for any nation to make it out of the underdevelopment trap. By the way, are we now to conclude that
Japan, Malaysia, Korea, etc. are guilty of exploitation just as the Western
powers are? If we aren’t, then the
diachronic indictment is just a moral shield for the ruling classes of the
Third World.
Again, advanced nations become net debtor nations. And again, Third-World nations solicit foreign investment and complain
because they do not get enough. That is
a reality which anyone in a position of governmental or managerial
responsibility — or even anyone in a graduate School of Public Administration
or Foreign Affairs — cannot deny or disregard.
We already saw that after the Left had carefully proved
that the wage bargain was slavery, its first demand was for more jobs, more slavery. Does it make
sense for the first demand of the poor nations to be for more investment? What are we to make of the stance of
excluding foreign capital which became axiomatic with Stalinist Communism, but
is now long forgotten? What are we to
make of the CMEA as a model of international economic relations?
At bottom, the diachronic indictment is a phase of
humanitarian indignation. It does not
have any norms. We don’t know how far
the rejectionism goes, whether it extends to the Scientific Revolution, whether
it extends to all of modernity (which was a strategic advantage for the
European peoples). The diachronic
indictment does not say whether it is anarchist. (I don’t want to be nasty to anarchism, but anarchism never made
a realized break from the bourgeois status quo except for an episode in
Barcelona which came to nothing.)
The diachronic indictment can’t tell you whether reform
redeems capitalism—or is only a bribe to forestall the revolution. It can’t tell you how much social relations
would have to change to become just.
As I said, it is face-value and undialectical. It is only capable of conceptualizing
reformist change. (It may fantasize
about battles won by bad-boy dictators, and rebellions which simply demolish
civilization. But—we may recall the two
Indian sackings of Mexico City in the seventeenth century—mere revenge does not
build a better society. Pure ferocity
cannot give the collectivity a life.)
It has no basis to conceptualize a prinicipled revolution—which depends
on knowing exactly what relations need to be replaced discontinuously by exactly what other relations.
•
H. The project of militant
theory revisited
Let me begin with a frankly amoral look at the
international economy, for astringent effect.
If one views the situation as if
the world had only come into being yesterday, how do we assume that there is a
problem?
There is a polarization of nations into rich nations and
poor nations, vaguely corresponding to a polarization of Northern and Southern
hemispheres. One part of the world is
far wealthier than another. But so
what? Can it meaningfully be said that
these discernable camps are opponents, or that one robs the other?
The advantage of the Northern hemisphere over the
Southern hemisphere is a wide-spectrum advantage. Banks, manufacturing corporations, “information conglomerates,”
intergovernmental financial institutions, regional economic associations, etc.,
pursue self-interested policies which synchronize to yield the observed
North-South polarization. It includes
everything from IMF-imposed financial gyrations to the manipulation of consumer
tastes and social structure in laggard nations.
No single mechanism of bilateral economic transactions
has thrust itself forward as the culprit.
Do you think direct private foreign investment is the mechanism for
pillaging the poorest countries? The
main recipient of U.S. investment is Canada.
Canada has prospered with a foreign-owned economy. The U.S. is now a net debtor nation. Is it oppressed by foreigners?
The same global capitalism will be with us for the
foreseeable future. Today, radicals
demand that the capitalist giants steer more investment to the Third World;
they demand a tighter embrace. Just as
they picture the remedy in the developed nations as job creation and growth of
labor productivity. Proposals have been
made for an anti-imperialist United Nations, for an income tax on developed
nations, for debt cancellation. These
proposals have not been accepted because the powerful are powerful enough to
withhold their consent.
The attempt to view long-term global shifts through a
moral lens founders because it cannot be translated into a feasible
politics. If there is no course of
action which will make the exploited feel that the world has been put right,
then it is harder to identify the pivot of the exploitation. Lenin said that foreign investment is
rape. But if a crowd demonstrates
demanding to be raped, then rape is no longer rape as far as politics is
concerned. The polarization of the
world into rich nations and poor nations does not establish for political
purposes that the rich nations rob the poor nations or even that rich nations
and poor nations have opposite interests.
A politically pivotal antagonism has not been focused.
As it happens, the escape from capitalism is not the
order of the day. That means that the
public understands “restoration of justice” as outdoing the winners at their
own game, or cutting in on the game, or moderating the rigors of commerce
politically. In the last case, we have
single-issue crusading, the sort of crusade through which unions and
humanitarians moderated capitalism in the developed nations. The economic theory behind such melioration
has to be an accusation of monopolistic practice by the First World, or a
sentimental preference for global equalization of incomes. These are the only “arguments for justice”
admitted in standard economics.
Whatever reforms come about, the strategic maneuvering continues,
and capitalism continues to prevail.
The next century’s leading event might be a shift of the capitalist
center back to Europe or on to the Pacific Rim. It would be another chapter in the meaningless circulation of
empires.
I do not rule out the possibility that modern
civilization is exhausted, notwithstanding the rapid technological change. That is why I attempted from the end of the
Sixties to bring my philosophical and political thought closer together. (An early example was “The Three Levels of
Politics” in Blueprint for a Higher
Civilization.) Escaping from the
blind alley of scientism, Eurosupremacism, linear progress.
• • •
References
J.A. Hobson, Imperialism (1902)
Rudolf Hilferding, Finance Capital
Rosa Luxemburg, The Accumulation of Capital (orig. 1913)
Karl
Kautsky, Nationalist State, Imperialist
State, and Union of States (orig. 1915)
Karl
Kautsky, Die Neue Zeit, 1913-14, II,
909; Die Neue Zeit, 1915-16, II, 107.
Rosa
Luxemburg, The Accumulation of Capital—An
Anti-Critique (orig. 1921)
Nikolai
Bukharin, Imperialism and the
Accumulation of Capital (orig. 1924)
Gunnar
Myrdal, Economic Theory and
Underdeveloped Regions (1957).
Raul Prebisch, The Economic Development of Latin America
(1950).
Raul
Prebisch, Towards a New Trade Policy for
Development (UN, 1964).
Raul Prebisch, Latin America: A Problem in Development (1971).
Shane
H. Mage, The Law of the Falling Tendency
of the Rate of Profit (1963, dissertation, Columbia University)
Pierre
Jalée, The Pillage of the Third World
(orig. 1965). HC59.7.J3513
Pierre
Jalée, The Third World in World Economy
(orig. 1968). HC59.7.J3613
Pierre Jalée, Imperialism in the Seventies (1972).
Pierre Jalée, How Capitalism Works (orig. 1974).
Arghiri Emmanuel, Unequal Exchange (originally 1969).
Alan
Hodgart, The Economics of European
Imperialism (1977) . HF1411.H.
Ian Steedman, Marx After Sraffa (1977).
Robert Paul Wolff, Understanding Marx (1984).
Samir Amin, Maldevelopment (1990).
Carl Parrini, "Theories of Imperialism," in Redefining the Past, ed. Lloyd Gardner (1986).
[1]Although the Cold War, which gave rise to this terminology, is over.
[2]The Econometric Approach to Development Planning (Chicago, 1965).
[3]I do not mention my own instructors at the New School, even though they have world reputations as radical economists (Hodgart lists Hymer), because their writings did not comprise militant theory.
[4]It is the same topic Hodgart’s book is devoted to, except that he is not remotely a militant theorist himself. He defines imperialism on page 75 as “the process by which economic growth might or might not be transmitted from advanced to backward nations.” It’s philanthopy, then.
[5]Standard economics does not frame the question like this, of course. It assumes that there is an absolute virtue called efficiency, and defines economics as the science of efficiency-seeking. The right price is the efficiency price. Economics devolves from a single pre-chosen virtue. Ironically, laissez-faire theorists also assert that a capitalist republic does not have a national goal.
[6]One would like to know what became of the Islamic law of usury in Iran during the Khomeini period. Was there some curtailment of banking not reported in the media?
[7]For powerful Leninist states, sovereignty was never a constraint.
[8]That is, I simply duplicated Marx as far as I could take it, without really settling the problem of whether Marx’s doctrine proves cogent as one puts more and more logical demands on it.
[9]Morishima, Steedman, Wolff, Roemer.
[10]Abstracting from corporate crime.
[11]The Accumulation of Capital. The Accumulation of Capital—An Anti-Critique.
[12]Forgetting that this word was literally invented by the Romans.
[13]Why did banking and capitalization become more important than the privately held manufacturing firm after the turn of the century? Why the export of manufactures to the Third World—after decades of accusations that they had been confined to raw materials production? Why no world depression after World War II? And so many other similar questions.
[14]J.K. Galbraith, The Affluent Society (1958).
[15]Cf. Lukacs’ essay on reification.
[16]Europeans become the “civic protagonists” of a non-European region. Australia, New Zealand, South Africa, North America, Argentina.
[17]Just the sort of claim which has never been substantiated satisfactorily.
[18]In a more familiar terminology, more concentrated.
[19]Even though mercantilist theory had already mandated opposite roles for metropolis and colony.